born c. 300 BC, Chao Kingdom, China died c. 230 BC, Lan-ling, Ch'u Kingdom, China Pinyin Xun-zi, also spelled Hsn-tze, original name Hsn K'uang, honorary name Hsn Ch'ing philosopher who was one of the three great Confucian philosophers of the Classical period in China. He elaborated and systematized the work undertaken by Confucius and Mencius, giving a cohesiveness, comprehensiveness, and direction to Confucian thought that was all the more compelling for the rigour with which he set it forth; and the strength he thereby gave to that philosophy has been largely responsible for its continuance as a living tradition for over 2,000 years. Many of his diverse intellectual achievements came to be obscured as later Confucians focused on the misanthropic view attributed to him that human nature is basically ugly or evil, and, beginning about the 12th century AD, his writings fell into a period of disfavour and neglect from which they have only recently reemerged. His original name was Hsn K'uang, but he is commonly referred to as Hsn-tzu (Master Hsn), tzu being an honorary suffix attached to the names of many philosophers. The exact dates of Hsn-tzu's life and career are uncertain. Little is known of his life save that he was a native of the state of Chao (in modern Shansi Province, north central China), that he belonged for some years to the Chi-hsia academy of philosophers maintained in Ch'i by the ruler of that eastern state, and that, later, because of slander, he moved south to the state of Ch'u, where he became magistrate of a small district in 255 BC and later died in retirement. Hsn-tzu's importance in the development of Confucian philosophy rests on the historical influence of his major work, known today as the Hsn-tzu. This book comprises 32 chapters, or essays, and is regarded as being in large part from his own hand, uncorrupted by later emendations or forgeries. The Hsn-tzu essays are a milestone in the development of Chinese philosophy. The anecdotal and epigrammatic style that had characterized earlier philosophical literaturei.e., the Analects, Tao-te Ching, Mencius, Chung-tzuno longer sufficed to convey fully and persuasively the complex philosophical disputes of Hsn-tzu's day. Hsn-tzu was the first great Confucian philosopher to express his ideas not merely by means of the sayings and conversations recorded by disciples but also in the form of well-organized essays written by himself. In his book he introduced a more rigorous writing style that emphasized topical development, sustained reasoning, detail, and clarity. Hsn-tzu's most famous dictum is that the nature of man is evil; his goodness is only acquired training. What Hsn-tzu preached was thus essentially a philosophy of culture. Human nature at birth, he maintained, consists of instinctual drives which, left to themselves, are selfish, anarchic, and antisocial. Society as a whole, however, exerts a civilizing influence upon the individual, gradually training and molding him until he becomes a disciplined and morally conscious human being. Of prime importance in this process are the li (ceremonies and ritual practices, rules of social behaviour, traditional mores) and music (which Hsn-tzu, like Plato, regarded as having a profound moral significance). Hsn-tzu's view of human nature was, of course, radically opposed to that of Mencius, who had optimistically proclaimed the innate goodness of man. Both thinkers agreed that all men are potentially capable of becoming sages, but for Mencius this meant that every man has it within his power to develop further the shoots of goodness already present at birth, whereas for Hsn-tzu it meant that every man can learn from society how to overcome his initially antisocial impulses. Thus began what became one of the major controversies in Confucian thought. The difference between Mencius and Hsn-tzu is metaphysical as well as ethical. T'ien (Heaven) for Mencius, though not an anthropomorphic deity, constituted an all-embracing ethical power; therefore it is inevitable that man's nature should be good, since he receives it from Heaven at birth. For Hsn-tzu, on the other hand, T'ien embodied no ethical principle and was simply the name for the functioning activities of the universe (somewhat like our word Nature). These activities he conceived of naturalistically and almost mechanistically. Moral standards, therefore, have no metaphysical justification but are man-made creations. One may ask how, if man is born evil (by which Hsn-tzu really meant uncivilized), it is possible for him to create the higher values of civilization. In the essay A Discussion of Ritual, Hsn-tzu attempts to answer this question and in the process elaborates the concept central to his entire philosophy. Hsn-tzu asserts that man differs from other creatures in one vital respect: besides his instinctual drives, he also possesses an intelligence which enables him to form cooperative social organizations. Hence the sages, realizing that man cannot well survive in a state of anarchy, used this intelligence to formulate the social distinctions and rules of social behaviour which would check the encroachments of one individual upon another and thereby ensure sufficiency for all. Hsn-tzu thus presents a believable utilitarian explanation for the creation of social institutions. The li constituted the Way of Confucianism as interpreted by Hsn-tzu, being the ritualized norms governing the mores, manners, and morals of the people. Originally the behavioral expressions of early supernatural beliefs, the historical li were being abandoned by an increasingly agnostic intelligentsia during Hsn-tzu's own era, the Warring States period, a time of great change and instability. Hsn-tzu had a sophisticated appreciation of the manifold advantages in areas such as trade, social mobility, and technology that were accompanying the breakdown of the feudal order during the Warring States period. At the same time, he could see that these societal transformations were also bringing to the Chinese the demise of their ancient socio-religious institutions, and he believed that the ritual practices (li) linked with those institutions were too important to be lost during secularization. For him, those ritual practices were important to the society because they were a culturally binding force for a people whose existence depended on cooperative economic efforts, and further, those ritual practices were important to the individual because they provided an aesthetic and spiritual dimension to the lives of the practitioners. By his fundamental insistence on the necessity of cultural continuity for both the physical and psychological well-being of his fellows, Hsn-tzu placed himself squarely in the ranks of Confucian philosophers and provided an ethical and aesthetic philosophical basis for these ritual practices as their religious foundation was weakening. The li are the basic stuff out of which Hsn-tzu builds the ideal society as described in his book, and the scholar-officials who are to govern that society have as their primary function the preservation and transmission of these ritual practices. Like all early Confucians, Hsn-tzu was opposed to hereditary privilege, advocating literacy and moral worth as the determinants of leadership positions, rather than birth or wealth; and these determinants were to have as their foundation a demonstrated knowledge of the high cultural traditionthe li. No less significant politically than socially, the li were to be employed by scholars to ensure that everyone was in a place, and officials were to employ the li to ensure that there was a place for everyone. Hsn-tzu's primary concern was with social philosophy and ethics, as evidenced by the content of his essays: 18 of the 32 fall solely within these areas, and the remainder fall partly so. Even the technical, linguistically oriented Rectification of Names is liberally sprinkled with comments about the adverse social consequences attending the abuse and misuse of language. Among his other famous essays, A Discussion of Music became the classic work on the subject in China. Here, too, social issues are under consideration as Hsn-tzu discusses the importance of music as a vehicle for expressing human emotions without generating interpersonal conflict. Another celebrated essay is A Discussion of Heaven, in which he attacks superstitious and supernatural beliefs. One of the work's main themes is that unusual natural phenomena (eclipses, etc.) are no less natural for their irregularityhence are not evil omensand therefore men should not be concerned at their occurrence. Hsn-tzu's denial of supernaturalism led him into a sophisticated interpretation of popular religious observances and superstitions. He asserted that these were merely poetic fictions, useful for the common people because they provided an orderly outlet for human emotions, but not to be taken as true by educated men. There Hsn-tzu inaugurated a rationalistic trend in Confucianism that has been congenial to scientific thinking. Hsn-tzu also made important contributions to psychology, semantics, education, logic, epistemology, and dialectic. Yet his primary interest in dialectic was as a tool for exposing the fallacies of rival schools, and he bitterly lamented the need for dialectic in the absence of a centralized political authority that could impose ideological unity from above. Hsn-tzu, indeed, was an authoritarian who formed a logical link between Confucianism and the totalitarian Legalists; it is no accident that among his students were two of the most famous Legalists, the theoretician Han Fei-tzu (c. 280233 BC) and the statesman Li Ssu (c. 280208 BC). Both of these men earned the enmity of later Confucian historians, and the opprobrium they have consistently received through the centuries has also negatively affected the evaluation of their teacher. Hsn-tzu's writings were no less the recipient of moral disapproval than his teaching, owing in large measure to the often-quoted essay Man's Nature Is Evil. Because Mencius believed that human beings were innately disposed toward moral behaviour, Hsn-tzu was perceived, as the author of this essay, to be attacking his illustrious predecessor. The truth is that Hsn-tzu remained Confucian in his firm rejection of the amoral philosophy and compulsive techniques of the Legalists, and in his insistence on Confucian morality as the basis for society. For several centuries after Hsn-tzu's death, his influence remained greater than that of Mencius. Only with the rise of Neo-Confucianism in the 10th century AD did his influence begin to wane, and not until the 12th century was the triumph of Mencius formalized by the inclusion of the Mencius among the Confucian classics and by Mencius' canonization as the second Sage of Confucianism. Hsn-tzu was declared heterodox. Hsn-tzu's model society was never put into practice, and, like Confucius and Mencius before him, he probably died believing himself to have been a failure. Yet the rationalism, religious skepticism, concern for man in society, historical and cultural sensitivity, and fondness for ancient lore and customs that pervade his writings also pervaded Chinese intellectual life for more than two millennia. No one dealt with these issues more thoroughly than Hsn-tzu, and his passionate defense of the Confucian moral vision contributed substantively to lessening the distance between the philosophical ideal and the historical reality. He has been correctly described as the molder of ancient Confucianism. Traditional China, with its extensive lands and huge population, came to be largely a Confucian statemaking Hsn-tzu one of the most influential philosophers the world has ever known. Additional reading Homer H. Dubs, Hsntze: The Moulder of Ancient Confucianism (1927, reissued 1966); Fung Yu-lan (Yu-lan Feng), A History of Chinese Philosophy, 2nd ed., vol. 1 (1952, reissued 1983); and A.S. Cua, Ethical Argumentation: A Study in Hsn Tzu's Moral Epistemology (1985).
HSUN-TZU
Meaning of HSUN-TZU in English
Britannica English vocabulary. Английский словарь Британика. 2012